2019-05
AUTHORSHan Li
ABSTRACTThe uniqueness thesis states that for any body of evidence and any proposition, there is at most one rational doxastic attitude that an epistemic agent can take toward that proposition. Permissivism is the denial of uniqueness. Perhaps the most popular form of permissivism is what I call the Epistemic Standard View (ESV), since it relies on the concept of epistemic standards. Roughly speaking, epistemic standards encode particular ways of responding to any possible body of evidence. Since different epistemic standards may rationalize different doxastic states on the same body of evidence, this view gives us a form of permissivism if different agents can have different epistemic standards. Defenders of the ESV, however, have not paid sufficient attention to what it means to have a particular epistemic standard. I argue that any theory of epistemic standard possession must satisfy two criteria to adequately address the broader needs of the ESV. The first criterion is the normative criterion: a theory of standard-possession should explain why agents are rationally required to form beliefs in accordance with their own (rational) epistemic standard, rather than any other (rational) standard. The second criterion is the applicability criterion: a theory of standard-possession should rule that agents have the epistemic standards we intuitively think they have. I then argue that no extant theories of standard-possession can satisfy both these criteria. I conclude by diagnosing why these criteria are so hard to jointly satisfy. Defenders of the ESV are thus left with a serious obstacle to forming a complete and plausible version of their view. More... »
PAGES1225-1245
http://scigraph.springernature.com/pub.10.1007/s11098-018-1055-1
DOIhttp://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1055-1
DIMENSIONShttps://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1101084346
JSON-LD is the canonical representation for SciGraph data.
TIP: You can open this SciGraph record using an external JSON-LD service: JSON-LD Playground Google SDTT
[
{
"@context": "https://springernature.github.io/scigraph/jsonld/sgcontext.json",
"about": [
{
"id": "http://purl.org/au-research/vocabulary/anzsrc-for/2008/1701",
"inDefinedTermSet": "http://purl.org/au-research/vocabulary/anzsrc-for/2008/",
"name": "Psychology",
"type": "DefinedTerm"
},
{
"id": "http://purl.org/au-research/vocabulary/anzsrc-for/2008/17",
"inDefinedTermSet": "http://purl.org/au-research/vocabulary/anzsrc-for/2008/",
"name": "Psychology and Cognitive Sciences",
"type": "DefinedTerm"
}
],
"author": [
{
"affiliation": {
"alternateName": "Kansas State University",
"id": "https://www.grid.ac/institutes/grid.36567.31",
"name": [
"Department of Philosophy, Kansas State University, 308C Dickens Hall, 66502, Manhattan, KS, USA"
],
"type": "Organization"
},
"familyName": "Li",
"givenName": "Han",
"type": "Person"
}
],
"citation": [
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9213.12065",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1002064221"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12006",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1003559162"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "sg:pub.10.1007/s11098-013-0231-6",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1009022234",
"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-013-0231-6"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.1111/0029-4624.35.s15.4",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1017282579"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2006-035",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1022842207"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1520-8583.2005.00069.x",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1032125584"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1520-8583.2005.00069.x",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1032125584"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "sg:pub.10.1007/s11098-015-0585-z",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1037034815",
"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0585-z"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12077",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1040416594"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "sg:pub.10.1007/s11229-011-9921-9",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1042882497",
"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9921-9"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.1080/00048408312341131",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1048467708"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "sg:pub.10.1007/s10670-013-9547-z",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1050333617",
"https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-013-9547-z"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.1086/288339",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1058598382"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzs007",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1059892539"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
},
{
"id": "https://doi.org/10.4159/harvard.9780674334236",
"sameAs": [
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1099274308"
],
"type": "CreativeWork"
}
],
"datePublished": "2019-05",
"datePublishedReg": "2019-05-01",
"description": "The uniqueness thesis states that for any body of evidence and any proposition, there is at most one rational doxastic attitude that an epistemic agent can take toward that proposition. Permissivism is the denial of uniqueness. Perhaps the most popular form of permissivism is what I call the Epistemic Standard View (ESV), since it relies on the concept of epistemic standards. Roughly speaking, epistemic standards encode particular ways of responding to any possible body of evidence. Since different epistemic standards may rationalize different doxastic states on the same body of evidence, this view gives us a form of permissivism if different agents can have different epistemic standards. Defenders of the ESV, however, have not paid sufficient attention to what it means to have a particular epistemic standard. I argue that any theory of epistemic standard possession must satisfy two criteria to adequately address the broader needs of the ESV. The first criterion is the normative criterion: a theory of standard-possession should explain why agents are rationally required to form beliefs in accordance with their own (rational) epistemic standard, rather than any other (rational) standard. The second criterion is the applicability criterion: a theory of standard-possession should rule that agents have the epistemic standards we intuitively think they have. I then argue that no extant theories of standard-possession can satisfy both these criteria. I conclude by diagnosing why these criteria are so hard to jointly satisfy. Defenders of the ESV are thus left with a serious obstacle to forming a complete and plausible version of their view.",
"genre": "research_article",
"id": "sg:pub.10.1007/s11098-018-1055-1",
"inLanguage": [
"en"
],
"isAccessibleForFree": false,
"isPartOf": [
{
"id": "sg:journal.1026678",
"issn": [
"0031-8116",
"1573-0883"
],
"name": "Philosophical Studies",
"type": "Periodical"
},
{
"issueNumber": "5",
"type": "PublicationIssue"
},
{
"type": "PublicationVolume",
"volumeNumber": "176"
}
],
"name": "The trouble with having standards",
"pagination": "1225-1245",
"productId": [
{
"name": "readcube_id",
"type": "PropertyValue",
"value": [
"c0c8740ae34abbf4654d24379df15dfac071da91a33644d2a21cf28fbdddc6da"
]
},
{
"name": "doi",
"type": "PropertyValue",
"value": [
"10.1007/s11098-018-1055-1"
]
},
{
"name": "dimensions_id",
"type": "PropertyValue",
"value": [
"pub.1101084346"
]
}
],
"sameAs": [
"https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1055-1",
"https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1101084346"
],
"sdDataset": "articles",
"sdDatePublished": "2019-04-11T13:24",
"sdLicense": "https://scigraph.springernature.com/explorer/license/",
"sdPublisher": {
"name": "Springer Nature - SN SciGraph project",
"type": "Organization"
},
"sdSource": "s3://com-uberresearch-data-dimensions-target-20181106-alternative/cleanup/v134/2549eaecd7973599484d7c17b260dba0a4ecb94b/merge/v9/a6c9fde33151104705d4d7ff012ea9563521a3ce/jats-lookup/v90/0000000369_0000000369/records_68962_00000001.jsonl",
"type": "ScholarlyArticle",
"url": "https://link.springer.com/10.1007%2Fs11098-018-1055-1"
}
]
Download the RDF metadata as: json-ld nt turtle xml License info
JSON-LD is a popular format for linked data which is fully compatible with JSON.
curl -H 'Accept: application/ld+json' 'https://scigraph.springernature.com/pub.10.1007/s11098-018-1055-1'
N-Triples is a line-based linked data format ideal for batch operations.
curl -H 'Accept: application/n-triples' 'https://scigraph.springernature.com/pub.10.1007/s11098-018-1055-1'
Turtle is a human-readable linked data format.
curl -H 'Accept: text/turtle' 'https://scigraph.springernature.com/pub.10.1007/s11098-018-1055-1'
RDF/XML is a standard XML format for linked data.
curl -H 'Accept: application/rdf+xml' 'https://scigraph.springernature.com/pub.10.1007/s11098-018-1055-1'
This table displays all metadata directly associated to this object as RDF triples.
106 TRIPLES
21 PREDICATES
41 URIs
19 LITERALS
7 BLANK NODES