Causality and Properties View Full Text


Ontology type: schema:Chapter     


Chapter Info

DATE

1980

AUTHORS

Sydney Shoemaker

ABSTRACT

It is events, rather then objects or properties, that are usually taken by philosophers to be the terms of the causal relationship. But an event typically consists of a change in the properties or relationships of one or more objects, the latter being what Jaegwon Kim has called the “constituent objects” of the event.1 And when one event causes another, this will be in part because of the properties possessed by their constituent objects. Suppose, for example, that a man takes a pill and, as a result, breaks out into a rash. Here the cause and effect are, respectively, the taking of the pill and the breaking out into a rash. Why did the first event cause the second? Well, the pill was penicillin, and the man was allergic to penicillin. No doubt one could want to know more — for example, about the biochemistry of allergies in general and this one in particular. But there is a good sense in which what has been said already explains why the one event caused the other. Here the pill and the man are the constituent objects of the cause event, and the man is the constituent object of the effect event. Following Kim we can also speak of events as having “constituent properties” and “constituent times”. In this case the constituent property of the cause event is the relation expressed by the verb ‘takes’, while the constituent property of the effect event is expressed by the predicate ‘breaks out into a rash’. The constituent times of the events are their times of occurrence. Specifying the constituent objects and properties of the cause and effect will tell us what these events consisted in, and together with a specification of their constituent times will serve to identify them; but it will not, typically, explain why the one brought about the other. We explain this by mentioning certain properties of their constituent objects. Given that the pill was penicillin, and that the man was allergic to penicillin, the taking of the pill by the man was certain, or at any rate very likely, to result in an allergic response like a rash. To take another example, suppose a branch is blown against a window and breaks it. Here the constituent objects include the branch and the window, and the causal relationship holds because of, among other things, the massiveness of the one and the fragility of the other. More... »

PAGES

109-135

References to SciGraph publications

  • 1972. Naming and Necessity in SEMANTICS OF NATURAL LANGUAGE
  • Book

    TITLE

    Time and Cause

    ISBN

    978-90-481-8358-6
    978-94-017-3528-5

    Author Affiliations

    Identifiers

    URI

    http://scigraph.springernature.com/pub.10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7

    DOI

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7

    DIMENSIONS

    https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1050324199


    Indexing Status Check whether this publication has been indexed by Scopus and Web Of Science using the SN Indexing Status Tool
    Incoming Citations Browse incoming citations for this publication using opencitations.net

    JSON-LD is the canonical representation for SciGraph data.

    TIP: You can open this SciGraph record using an external JSON-LD service: JSON-LD Playground Google SDTT

    [
      {
        "@context": "https://springernature.github.io/scigraph/jsonld/sgcontext.json", 
        "about": [
          {
            "id": "http://purl.org/au-research/vocabulary/anzsrc-for/2008/1701", 
            "inDefinedTermSet": "http://purl.org/au-research/vocabulary/anzsrc-for/2008/", 
            "name": "Psychology", 
            "type": "DefinedTerm"
          }, 
          {
            "id": "http://purl.org/au-research/vocabulary/anzsrc-for/2008/17", 
            "inDefinedTermSet": "http://purl.org/au-research/vocabulary/anzsrc-for/2008/", 
            "name": "Psychology and Cognitive Sciences", 
            "type": "DefinedTerm"
          }
        ], 
        "author": [
          {
            "affiliation": {
              "alternateName": "Cornell University", 
              "id": "https://www.grid.ac/institutes/grid.5386.8", 
              "name": [
                "Cornell University, USA"
              ], 
              "type": "Organization"
            }, 
            "familyName": "Shoemaker", 
            "givenName": "Sydney", 
            "type": "Person"
          }
        ], 
        "citation": [
          {
            "id": "sg:pub.10.1007/978-94-010-2557-7_9", 
            "sameAs": [
              "https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1032339565", 
              "https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2557-7_9"
            ], 
            "type": "CreativeWork"
          }, 
          {
            "id": "https://doi.org/10.2307/2023853", 
            "sameAs": [
              "https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1069703233"
            ], 
            "type": "CreativeWork"
          }
        ], 
        "datePublished": "1980", 
        "datePublishedReg": "1980-01-01", 
        "description": "It is events, rather then objects or properties, that are usually taken by philosophers to be the terms of the causal relationship. But an event typically consists of a change in the properties or relationships of one or more objects, the latter being what Jaegwon Kim has called the \u201cconstituent objects\u201d of the event.1 And when one event causes another, this will be in part because of the properties possessed by their constituent objects. Suppose, for example, that a man takes a pill and, as a result, breaks out into a rash. Here the cause and effect are, respectively, the taking of the pill and the breaking out into a rash. Why did the first event cause the second? Well, the pill was penicillin, and the man was allergic to penicillin. No doubt one could want to know more \u2014 for example, about the biochemistry of allergies in general and this one in particular. But there is a good sense in which what has been said already explains why the one event caused the other. Here the pill and the man are the constituent objects of the cause event, and the man is the constituent object of the effect event. Following Kim we can also speak of events as having \u201cconstituent properties\u201d and \u201cconstituent times\u201d. In this case the constituent property of the cause event is the relation expressed by the verb \u2018takes\u2019, while the constituent property of the effect event is expressed by the predicate \u2018breaks out into a rash\u2019. The constituent times of the events are their times of occurrence. Specifying the constituent objects and properties of the cause and effect will tell us what these events consisted in, and together with a specification of their constituent times will serve to identify them; but it will not, typically, explain why the one brought about the other. We explain this by mentioning certain properties of their constituent objects. Given that the pill was penicillin, and that the man was allergic to penicillin, the taking of the pill by the man was certain, or at any rate very likely, to result in an allergic response like a rash. To take another example, suppose a branch is blown against a window and breaks it. Here the constituent objects include the branch and the window, and the causal relationship holds because of, among other things, the massiveness of the one and the fragility of the other.", 
        "editor": [
          {
            "familyName": "Van Inwagen", 
            "givenName": "Peter", 
            "type": "Person"
          }
        ], 
        "genre": "chapter", 
        "id": "sg:pub.10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7", 
        "inLanguage": [
          "en"
        ], 
        "isAccessibleForFree": false, 
        "isPartOf": {
          "isbn": [
            "978-90-481-8358-6", 
            "978-94-017-3528-5"
          ], 
          "name": "Time and Cause", 
          "type": "Book"
        }, 
        "name": "Causality and Properties", 
        "pagination": "109-135", 
        "productId": [
          {
            "name": "doi", 
            "type": "PropertyValue", 
            "value": [
              "10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7"
            ]
          }, 
          {
            "name": "readcube_id", 
            "type": "PropertyValue", 
            "value": [
              "efbb143d176e45346ef97d79e6eec05674e7a0fe19202088eacdeaed5a649011"
            ]
          }, 
          {
            "name": "dimensions_id", 
            "type": "PropertyValue", 
            "value": [
              "pub.1050324199"
            ]
          }
        ], 
        "publisher": {
          "location": "Dordrecht", 
          "name": "Springer Netherlands", 
          "type": "Organisation"
        }, 
        "sameAs": [
          "https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7", 
          "https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1050324199"
        ], 
        "sdDataset": "chapters", 
        "sdDatePublished": "2019-04-15T12:35", 
        "sdLicense": "https://scigraph.springernature.com/explorer/license/", 
        "sdPublisher": {
          "name": "Springer Nature - SN SciGraph project", 
          "type": "Organization"
        }, 
        "sdSource": "s3://com-uberresearch-data-dimensions-target-20181106-alternative/cleanup/v134/2549eaecd7973599484d7c17b260dba0a4ecb94b/merge/v9/a6c9fde33151104705d4d7ff012ea9563521a3ce/jats-lookup/v90/0000000001_0000000264/records_8663_00000274.jsonl", 
        "type": "Chapter", 
        "url": "http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7"
      }
    ]
     

    Download the RDF metadata as:  json-ld nt turtle xml License info

    HOW TO GET THIS DATA PROGRAMMATICALLY:

    JSON-LD is a popular format for linked data which is fully compatible with JSON.

    curl -H 'Accept: application/ld+json' 'https://scigraph.springernature.com/pub.10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7'

    N-Triples is a line-based linked data format ideal for batch operations.

    curl -H 'Accept: application/n-triples' 'https://scigraph.springernature.com/pub.10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7'

    Turtle is a human-readable linked data format.

    curl -H 'Accept: text/turtle' 'https://scigraph.springernature.com/pub.10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7'

    RDF/XML is a standard XML format for linked data.

    curl -H 'Accept: application/rdf+xml' 'https://scigraph.springernature.com/pub.10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7'


     

    This table displays all metadata directly associated to this object as RDF triples.

    71 TRIPLES      23 PREDICATES      29 URIs      20 LITERALS      8 BLANK NODES

    Subject Predicate Object
    1 sg:pub.10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7 schema:about anzsrc-for:17
    2 anzsrc-for:1701
    3 schema:author N7415ec97620f455bace8c08ae557e28a
    4 schema:citation sg:pub.10.1007/978-94-010-2557-7_9
    5 https://doi.org/10.2307/2023853
    6 schema:datePublished 1980
    7 schema:datePublishedReg 1980-01-01
    8 schema:description It is events, rather then objects or properties, that are usually taken by philosophers to be the terms of the causal relationship. But an event typically consists of a change in the properties or relationships of one or more objects, the latter being what Jaegwon Kim has called the “constituent objects” of the event.1 And when one event causes another, this will be in part because of the properties possessed by their constituent objects. Suppose, for example, that a man takes a pill and, as a result, breaks out into a rash. Here the cause and effect are, respectively, the taking of the pill and the breaking out into a rash. Why did the first event cause the second? Well, the pill was penicillin, and the man was allergic to penicillin. No doubt one could want to know more — for example, about the biochemistry of allergies in general and this one in particular. But there is a good sense in which what has been said already explains why the one event caused the other. Here the pill and the man are the constituent objects of the cause event, and the man is the constituent object of the effect event. Following Kim we can also speak of events as having “constituent properties” and “constituent times”. In this case the constituent property of the cause event is the relation expressed by the verb ‘takes’, while the constituent property of the effect event is expressed by the predicate ‘breaks out into a rash’. The constituent times of the events are their times of occurrence. Specifying the constituent objects and properties of the cause and effect will tell us what these events consisted in, and together with a specification of their constituent times will serve to identify them; but it will not, typically, explain why the one brought about the other. We explain this by mentioning certain properties of their constituent objects. Given that the pill was penicillin, and that the man was allergic to penicillin, the taking of the pill by the man was certain, or at any rate very likely, to result in an allergic response like a rash. To take another example, suppose a branch is blown against a window and breaks it. Here the constituent objects include the branch and the window, and the causal relationship holds because of, among other things, the massiveness of the one and the fragility of the other.
    9 schema:editor N9e0962d8d5074b9594ed7f29c3683fe6
    10 schema:genre chapter
    11 schema:inLanguage en
    12 schema:isAccessibleForFree false
    13 schema:isPartOf Nd4a7c17a5a834f32bb5e195358a43f0c
    14 schema:name Causality and Properties
    15 schema:pagination 109-135
    16 schema:productId N377f84d9f2bf473d8c51e04431274f34
    17 N96f71900053a4694b9a5e829db1ffa52
    18 Ne2569e60f1df40fea7bc2f5969758675
    19 schema:publisher N193d0ef1db0c45c387c1755487316b29
    20 schema:sameAs https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1050324199
    21 https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7
    22 schema:sdDatePublished 2019-04-15T12:35
    23 schema:sdLicense https://scigraph.springernature.com/explorer/license/
    24 schema:sdPublisher Nbd62fac2b39c43e199eaf67e491fdb86
    25 schema:url http://link.springer.com/10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7
    26 sgo:license sg:explorer/license/
    27 sgo:sdDataset chapters
    28 rdf:type schema:Chapter
    29 N160e3c8431674f1c946d0e6c5b83f958 schema:affiliation https://www.grid.ac/institutes/grid.5386.8
    30 schema:familyName Shoemaker
    31 schema:givenName Sydney
    32 rdf:type schema:Person
    33 N193d0ef1db0c45c387c1755487316b29 schema:location Dordrecht
    34 schema:name Springer Netherlands
    35 rdf:type schema:Organisation
    36 N1cc3718d1bc34588be003a7a23ab3aa9 schema:familyName Van Inwagen
    37 schema:givenName Peter
    38 rdf:type schema:Person
    39 N377f84d9f2bf473d8c51e04431274f34 schema:name doi
    40 schema:value 10.1007/978-94-017-3528-5_7
    41 rdf:type schema:PropertyValue
    42 N7415ec97620f455bace8c08ae557e28a rdf:first N160e3c8431674f1c946d0e6c5b83f958
    43 rdf:rest rdf:nil
    44 N96f71900053a4694b9a5e829db1ffa52 schema:name dimensions_id
    45 schema:value pub.1050324199
    46 rdf:type schema:PropertyValue
    47 N9e0962d8d5074b9594ed7f29c3683fe6 rdf:first N1cc3718d1bc34588be003a7a23ab3aa9
    48 rdf:rest rdf:nil
    49 Nbd62fac2b39c43e199eaf67e491fdb86 schema:name Springer Nature - SN SciGraph project
    50 rdf:type schema:Organization
    51 Nd4a7c17a5a834f32bb5e195358a43f0c schema:isbn 978-90-481-8358-6
    52 978-94-017-3528-5
    53 schema:name Time and Cause
    54 rdf:type schema:Book
    55 Ne2569e60f1df40fea7bc2f5969758675 schema:name readcube_id
    56 schema:value efbb143d176e45346ef97d79e6eec05674e7a0fe19202088eacdeaed5a649011
    57 rdf:type schema:PropertyValue
    58 anzsrc-for:17 schema:inDefinedTermSet anzsrc-for:
    59 schema:name Psychology and Cognitive Sciences
    60 rdf:type schema:DefinedTerm
    61 anzsrc-for:1701 schema:inDefinedTermSet anzsrc-for:
    62 schema:name Psychology
    63 rdf:type schema:DefinedTerm
    64 sg:pub.10.1007/978-94-010-2557-7_9 schema:sameAs https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1032339565
    65 https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2557-7_9
    66 rdf:type schema:CreativeWork
    67 https://doi.org/10.2307/2023853 schema:sameAs https://app.dimensions.ai/details/publication/pub.1069703233
    68 rdf:type schema:CreativeWork
    69 https://www.grid.ac/institutes/grid.5386.8 schema:alternateName Cornell University
    70 schema:name Cornell University, USA
    71 rdf:type schema:Organization
     




    Preview window. Press ESC to close (or click here)


    ...